~by David Aiken~
We live in a time
subjugated by ‘Hallmark Cards’ pseudo- or pop-philosophy, and wir
Philosophen, as Nietzsche would have said, “we philosophers,” should
definitely be engaged in the quest of examining, eternally and recurrently, the
various aspects of this our present maudlin Zeitgeist. The Days of our
Lives are being interpreted for us through a lens of sugarcoated fancies. And
through our rose-tinted sentimentalist glasses we perceive a world-of-men
thoroughly, but implausibly, saturated with saccharine notions of joy &
happiness, love & marriage, and ever ready to hum along with the nanny, “raindrops on roses and whiskers on kittens…”
Then, when we finally stride across the threshold of simple-minded belief to
enter into the torrential onslaught of Real-Life,
we seem startled to find ourselves roaming around the quagmires of an
intellectual Wasteland. And slowly, ever-so-painfully-slowly, we realize that we are
also troubled by another disturbing ditty that has begun haunting our
footsteps, and which sounds strangely familiar, like something Bilbo Baggins
might have softly hummed upon leaving his beloved Shire:
The
Road goes ever on and on
Down
from the door where it began.
Now
far ahead the Road has gone,
And
I must follow, if I can,
Pursuing
it with eager feet,
Until
it joins some larger way
Where
many paths and errands meet.
And
whither then? I cannot say.
Now
it may well be that Life is like a box of chocolates, as Mrs. Gump one day informed
her naïve young son, Forrest; one could just never know what one was going to get. But
surely Life seems much more like an exchange with a Cheshire Cat—ONE DAY Alice
finds herself wandering around on an Adventure in Wonderland, and so many people
seem to her a bit daft… but then she meets a puss from Cheshire that, maybe by
way of wanting to comfort her, explains that in fact everyone is mad, to
which Alice responds:
But
I don't want to go among mad people"(...)
"Oh, you can't help that," said the Cat: "we're all mad here. I'm mad. You're mad."
"How do you know I'm mad?" said Alice.
"You must be," said the Cat, "or you wouldn't have come here."
"Oh, you can't help that," said the Cat: "we're all mad here. I'm mad. You're mad."
"How do you know I'm mad?" said Alice.
"You must be," said the Cat, "or you wouldn't have come here."
The conversation
goes downhill from there, of course, when, as Alice politely asks for
directions: "Would you tell me, please, which way I ought to go from
here?" the Cat laconically responds:
"That depends a good deal on where you want
to get to" (…).
"I don’t much care where--" said Alice.
"Then it doesn’t matter which way you go," said the Cat.
"--so long as I get SOMEWHERE," Alice added as an explanation.
"Oh, you’re sure to do that," said the Cat, "if you only walk long enough."
"I don’t much care where--" said Alice.
"Then it doesn’t matter which way you go," said the Cat.
"--so long as I get SOMEWHERE," Alice added as an explanation.
"Oh, you’re sure to do that," said the Cat, "if you only walk long enough."
Which
brings us right the way ‘round to our meander in the intellectual Wastelands of
the world-of-men, and to our question about whether Happiness is really the
syrupy kind of subjective past-time suggested by the countless voices of our
Zeitgeist. Is Happiness a value or a virtue? Is it a goal to be pursued? Is it
even desirable to be happy? Opinions abound.
But just to problematize the question un tantinet
reductively, let us consider whether Hitler, Time Magazine’s 1939 Man of the Year, was a happy camper as he was planning and
then setting into motion the new Reich’s takeover of the knowable universe. Now
just the idea of a Happy Hitler is generally enough to induce a pukefest in the
normal John Q. Citizen of the democratic variety. Yet the answer to our
question is undoubtedly “yes,” upon appropriate study and reflection, even though most of us prefer to believe
that Hitler was one sick f&%# and that he definitely could not have been happy—not really!
So, just intuitively and just maybe it
might perhaps begin to dawn on us that Happiness, which at first blush might be
thought to be a value in and of itself, probably is not; and that we should
take the time to rethink its position on our virtue/value list!
The
point to our little excursion into our crazed social imagination is to suggest
that, despite its quasi-unassailable status as an Iconic Idea in the popular
view, Happiness per se has no universal definition or value upon which we all
might conveniently agree. It is both obvious and inescapable that one man’s
happiness can easily be another man’s misery. Indeed, this is precisely the
philosophical rub.
The
text that serves as the primary springboard for our reflection is from the
second section of the Declaration of Independence (adopted July 4, 1776), in which Thomas Jefferson
(1743-1826) posits the following: “We hold these truths to be self-evident,
that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their creator with
certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty, and the pursuit
of Happiness.”
First,
though, is it even possible for us Moderns to reconstruct with any precision
what the early American philosophe was thinking when he penned the
Declarative and Independently minded expression, ‘the pursuit of Happiness’?
Well, in addition to the infinite number and variety of pop-philosophical
cultural opinions on the question of Happiness, there are also at least three
reasoned schools of scholarly opinion on the question of what ideas were
informing the 3rd U.S. President as he penned these famous and, for
us Moderns, famously woolly words. As always, though, scholarly debate is worth
just about what you would pay to go hear it, and there is a voice for every
viewpoint—the good, the bad, and the lame.
One
good opinion, which I happen to favor personally, concerns Jefferson, the
philosopher of Epicurean or Stoic thought. Stoicism teaches that personal
happiness is integrally allied to self-control or self-governance (cf.
Jefferson, vol. XV, 219ff. of the 1903 Library Edition). Jefferson writes in
especially enthusiastic terms of Stoic Thinking as it was handed down in the
writings of Epictetus, and even considered doing a new translation, “for
[Epictetus] has never been tolerably translated into English.” A point on which
he and I are in copious agreement.
On Epicurus and Stoic moral thinking,
Jefferson sets forth the following formulaic definitions (XV, 223ff): Happiness
= the aim of life; Virtue = the foundation of happiness; Utility
= the test of virtue; Pleasure = active and Indolent; and Indolence
= the absence of pain. By Indolence, it is clear from the context that
Jefferson is referring both to the idea of body indolence, from the Latin indolentia,
which is to be free from bodily pain, as well as to the Stoic notion of ataraxia,
or the tranquility of mind that characterizes someone who is free from worry
and distress.
The influence of Stoic philosophy was
widespread among early American philosophes, and clearly also informed the
thinking of the roughly contemporary American philosopher Ralph Waldo Emerson
(1803-1882), which is evident in his famous essay, Self Reliance.
This well-documented and pervasive Stoic connection, of course, would seem
strongly to suggest that Jefferson’s “pursuit of Happiness” should best be
construed as a personal philosophical attitude of Independence of Mind toward
the world-of-men.
Very
predictably, however, there is also a second scholarly school of thought on
this question—that it is rather the English Enlightenment philosopher and
empiricist, John Locke (1632-1704), who informs both Emerson’s as well as
Jefferson’s thinking, and that Jefferson’s “pursuit of Happiness” is best
understood in terms of Enlightenment empiricism imported from England. This is
a plausible consideration, and is indeed representative of the mainstream
scholarly opinion—that the Jeffersonian “pursuit of Happiness” derives from
Locke’s political philosophy and is best interpreted in that light.
To be sure, this is certainly a scholarly
opinion; although it is arguably feeble. In each of Jefferson’s references to
Locke (cf. Jefferson, vols. VIII, 31; XI, 222; XV, 266; and XVI, 19) he speaks,
almost nonchalantly, about Locke the materialist; and while he makes specific
references to Locke’s writings, categorizing Locke as ‘the man to read’, Jefferson’s
enthusiasm on the subject is certainly, well, stoically restrained. This stands
in stark contrast to the glowing and vigorous recommendations he gives for the
Stoic philosophers, praising both specific thinkers as well as the moral
tradition.
What one can find perhaps
most persuasive in the argument for a Lockean influence on Jefferson’s “pursuit of Happiness” is, first,
that Jefferson clearly says that Locke is the go-to philosopher for wonderful
ideas on materialism, which interests Jefferson as an alternative philosophical
framing to the normative Christian worldview.
Even more interesting
as an unstated argument, however, is Jefferson’s reliance upon Lockian language-music
in his creation of the Declaration of Independence. Locke defines
property as a person's
"life, liberty, and estate." That is a catchy bit of writing from Mr.
Locke, rhythmically speaking; and Jefferson’s writing is in no wise inferior
when he writes concerning certain unalienable Rights, among which "are
Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness.” Yet it also seems almost
gratuitous to point out that, although it is obvious that Jefferson liked and
borrowed the rhythm of Locke’s phrasing, he nevertheless disagreed with
the idea of the phrase, thus changing Locke’s English “and estate,” to
the American “pursuit of Happiness.”
There
is at least one other mainstream scholarly opinion on the question of how to
interpret Jefferson’s “pursuit of Happiness,” which is advanced by the
historian Garry Wills; but this opinion seems to limp a little
too much through the arcane and recherché to be persuasive in the
context of this reflection.
§ Wind-up.
Additional philosophical support for the interpretation that the “pursuit of
Happiness” is best understood as a personal philosophical attitude of
Independence of Mind, might also come from Aristotle’s notion of eudaimonia—what
Heraclitus might have translated as the well-demoned or well-daimoned life. Let it be said, however, that while
there are certainly traces of Aristotle in Jefferson’s writings, relevant to
politics, republics, and materialism, there is no indication that he was in any
way inspired by the Stagirite’s Virtue Ethic.
For the General
Record, though, and because we are reflecting on the question of Happiness as
an Idea, it was Aristotle’s contention that we should actually thrive in our lives. Even more, though, according to Aristotle this eudaimoniac-thriving,
which we Moderns generally translate as happiness, is in fact the ultimate
purpose of human existence. Aristotle’s eudaimonia is linguistically
reminiscent of the Socratic Daimon; and we must remember that it is Socrates
who gave moral direction both to that philosopher and to Stoic thought in
general.
So, even beyond
Jefferson’s Declarative Announcement in its favor, there are many philosophical
reasons for why Happiness or Thriving or Independence of Mind should come to
occupy a prominent place in our hearts and thoughts as a Philosophical Value.
Nevertheless, once the foundations of right thinking (read: Philosophy) give
way to populist fancies, definitions for ideas such as Happiness become much
fuzzier, and we Moderns are left with questions, such as: What does happiness mean to you?, which do not necessarily lead us to
meaningful answers, because they also lead us to the admission that Hitler was
undoubtedly as happy as a Nazi clam. Any answer to this type of fuzzy question
is, philosophically speaking, a castle built on sand.
So, is there more
to life than being happy? There are indeed some scientists out there “who are cautioning against the pursuit of mere happiness”; and others who suggest in the same vein that trying too hard to be happy
in fact makes us unhappy. Philosophically, however, it might be argued that
such an understanding, and therefore research grounded in that understanding,
is fatally flawed by Science’s fundamental mis-understanding about the
essentially philosophical (read: non-empirical) nature of the question. But
then again, just like all the rest of us, scientists are also subject to
“zeitgeistic” opinions and attitudes about happiness, and to the sweepingly
sugarcoated, saccharine-fueled sentimentalism that continually seeks to
supersede the hard work of Informed Thinking.
To
answer this question in kind: For us Moderns, at least in the U.S., who have
been nurtured directly or indirectly on the Jeffersonian notion of We the
People, is it possible for us to conceive as meaningful, philosophically
speaking, an individual life where Thriving, either in body or in mind, is
dislocated from the individual life? Or is it possible, philosophically
speaking, to conceive of as meaningful a personal life where the individual is
called to yield up his Independence of Mind, or where his I of M is
trained out of him through tutelage in an impoverished educational system?
Would this not be tantamount to an unintentional Abolition of the Cogito, which Heidegger actually intentionally argues for in Being
and Time? But this implies the disintegration of the Enlightenment Individual,
which must inevitably leave us, both as individuals and as a people, vulnerable
to every possible form of totalitarian regime?
In and through his
Enlightenment writings Jefferson crafted a philosophical Model of the Reasoning
Man, into whose hands he put the reins of Political Power. And the only real
burden he placed on this Reasoning Man is that he should be educated, in the
sense that he should be informed about Things of State. Because there is
nothing more appalling to Reason than to put power over the lives of ‘We the
People’ into the hands of those who choose a path of willful ignorance and
self-service.
Is there more to
life than being happy? If, by happiness, one means to affirm the Individual as
Self-governing Thinking-Thing moving toward the Virtue of reason, then, no,
there can be nothing greater in life. Following in a long line of earlier and
like-minded Stoic philosophers, Jefferson invites us to welcome and embrace
Happiness as a Virtuous Habit of the well-demoned Mind, so that we might be
faithful in working to secure for ourselves, and then perhaps for the world,
those certain unalienable Rights, among which are Life, Liberty and the pursuit
of this Happiness.
(Original essay
reprised and reworked from Phrontisterion, June 2013)
Further
Phrontisterion reading on Stoicism:
No comments:
Post a Comment