Showing posts with label The Republic. Show all posts
Showing posts with label The Republic. Show all posts

Sunday, November 1, 2020

The Space of a Man


~by David Aiken~

 

Borders & Edges.

            Every-thing is just so frustratingly approximative—so imprecise and fluctuating in a very-vague kind of way. This is true of all things, of those things of a physis sort (re: nature & the natural) as with things of a kosmos sort (re: intellect & the interpretative).  For a refresher course on this distinction, have a look at the Phrontisterion essay on Anti-conversion in “An Existential Moment” (February 2013).

         

   Trying to determine the exact boundaries or edges of physical things, for example, which seem so very clear and so very observably present to our senses, is notoriously difficult in this rather hazy kind of world of ours. The classical illustration of this idea for students of philosophy is the good old-fashioned table (or chair): my body tells me that the table is one sort of a thing—it is solid, ponderously weighty, and does not seem to be going anywhere at any given speed; it seems to just want to hang out in the space that it presently occupies. In contrast, however, my mind tells me that the table is also a constituted, and therefore composed kind of ‘event’—it is made up of an unimaginable number of invisible, itsy-bity teeny-weeny other-things that are all zinging around at warp-speed, and which are not at all concrete and stationary like the table-thing of which they are the composing elements. Now which of these two tables, the one that is speaking to my body or the one that is comprehended by my mind, is the most nearly-true definition of this particular table at which I sit and write? It seems obvious that both ‘truths’ are somehow implicated in the ‘thing’ that is this table, but only one of the truths is actually experienced by me. From one point of view—the body’s, the edges of the table seem quite distinct from the edges of me the writer, but from a second point of view—the mind’s, both the table and I seem inseparably implicated in the dance of sub-physical, invisible other-reality that frames the symphonic composition of things-in-the-world that are even now presenting themselves to our senses as visible and therefore stable. As World

            In contrast to our table, language is obviously a very cosmetic (i.e., from kosmos) sort of thing. And although it is the primary tool by means of which humans speak out their recognition of the world, it is also perhaps one of the more disturbingly approximative forms of identifying and articulating object-events. One has only to look at the idea of denotations and connotations, which sets the boundaries for words. The denotative world of a word is actually quite straitjacketed and narrow, and has therefore at least some degree of precision because it is more exclusive, while a word’s connotative world is infinitely richer and inclusive, brimming with associative images and suggestions, and overflowing with emotional and figurative relationships. The word ‘invitation’, for example, is denotatively a “written or verbal request inviting someone to go somewhere or to do something,” as in a wedding or birthday party invitation. Connotatively, however, an ‘invitation’ lives in an entirely different space –it is an incitement to venture out into strange new corridors of the world, a bidding to try new things, a giving of permission to go through doors that stand open but which may, at first blush, seem to us forbidding and ominous.

 

Toward Enlightenment.

            In the historical intervals that have followed upon the heels of Enlightenment in the West, we are offered rare glimpses into an interpretative world, a kosmos, that is almost entirely illuminated and articulated by purely human categories of thinking. Enlightenment created ‘The Individual’. This was obviously the case in the first period of Western Enlightenment in ancient Greece, which gave rise to philosophy as the very first human scientia of things natural, and also in the second period of enlightenment in 18th century Europe, which superintended the fairly radical dethronement of the Religious Mind, and the gradual enthronement of the rational and thoroughly human Mind as the measure and meaning-giver of man in his world.

            In the first period of Western Enlightenment, the “Space” where The Individual “happens” (—for there are some philosophers who make the case that Socrates was in fact the West’s first individual and that he taught a philosophy where the individual mattered as individuum—) can be measured on a gradation that separates two influential Greek thinkers from the classical period: on the extreme rationalist end of our Scale of Individuality there is the Greek architect-philosopher, Hippodamus (498-408 BC), who originally hailed from Miletus in Asia Minor, and on the spiritualizing end of that scale there is the famous Athenian philosopher, Plato (ca. 428-347 BC).

            According to the Wiki-world on Hippodamus, we discover how, through this first urban planner, Man presumed to impose upon the real topography of the real physical world of hills & valleys and streams & rivers, the rationalizing and abstracted geographical grid-frames of strictly human and cosmetic thought. This was the birthright of rationalism, perhaps already at its worst.

Hippodamus… was an ancient Greek architect, urban planner, physician, mathematician, meteorologist and philosopher and is considered to be the “father” of urban planning, the namesake of Hippodamian plan of city layouts (grid plan). […] According to Aristotle, Hippodamus was the first author who wrote upon the theory of government, without any knowledge of practical affairs. His plans of Greek cities were characterised by order and regularity in contrast to the intricacy and confusion common to cities of that period, even Athens. He is seen as the originator of the idea that a town plan might formally embody and clarify a rational social order.

 

On the other hand, although his dialogue The Republic has been almost entirely co-opted by political philosophers and re-constructed as some kind of feeble humbuggery disguised as a rational ‘theory of state’, Plato in fact allegorizes for us in The Republic, through the analogy of the State, the interior structures—the types of Souls—that can be found among Individual Men. Parenthetically, however, neither this idea nor this metaphor originates with Plato, because we find already a earlier incarnation of both in the nature poem of the Pre-Socratic philosopher-poet, Parmenides. Or, in the even more ancient notion of Hindu castes.

            If we follow out the broad strokes of the narrative in Plato’s Republic, though, Plato’s initiatory intent throughout his mythical “republican” allegory becomes obvious, an idea that can be said to be confirmed through later usage not only by the Christian apostle, Paul, who appropriated and employed the structure of that allegory to good effect in his New Testament letter to the Church in Corinth (I Corinthians 15:45ff), but also through usage by later Neo-Platonic philosophers, such as the late 5th century Boethius, who, in Book IV of the Consolation of Philosophy, divides man’s life journey into either a descent toward the embodiment of the life of the beasts (evil) or an ascent toward becoming gods (good).

            At a very basic level, in his Republic Plato means to portray for us, in the Gyges myth (Book II), the ‘earthy’ man (Paul’s psychikon or soulish man, i.e., a man like the First Adam/Man; I Cor. 15:46-47) who burrows into the earth and discovers, but does not grasp the importance of, the limitations of earthly dreams and aspirations. Allegorically speaking, as an alternative to the life of burrowing and tunneling into the bowels of the earth, Plato tells us in Book VII a second story in the form of an allegory, the well-known allegory of the Cave, where we learn about the second man, who seeks enlightenment (Paul’s pneumatikon or heavenly/spiritual man, a man like the Second Adam/Man; I Cor. 15:46-47), who struggles to free himself from the earthly Cave, and who, during his ascent out of the earth-womb, discovers the higher and indeed the highest truths in, about, and behind the World. In Plato’s final myth in the Republic (Book X), we discover a character, a Phoenician, whose name is Er. In this last republican myth Plato hopes for the Reader to understand that the choice is given to each of us as to how to live, either as the earthy man or the sky-bound man—the only choice that necessity imposes upon us is that we necessarily must choose the direction of our journey: either our lives will be as diggers and burrowers in the darkness, or as climbers toward the sunlight and the stars. Choose—we must; but in which direction? That is both the reader’s rub, and the philosophical reason behind Plato’s writing of the Republic!

            For the philosophical comparison in a history-of-ideas kind of way, Plato’s earthy man or sky-bound man are also conceptually anticipated (QED) in Jainism, in the Śvētāmbara (White-clad) and Digambara (sky-clad) traditions.

 

The one constant in the enlightened Greece of antiquity is the shift of philosophers and poets away from narratives that are grounded in stories about the gods. And in that shifting away from the Religious Mind, it is possible for us to cherry-pick illustrations of those thinkers who leaned toward the rationalizing interpretative framework of Hippodamus just as easily as one can find illustrations for those who tended to spiritualize Man after the way of Plato and his followers.

 

In the second period of Western enlightenment, the “Space” of The Individual is measurable by the progression of the democratic ideal from its small Western cradle to its pervasively global nesting grounds; and the cornerstone for this enlightenment vision is, obviously, the idea of The Individual. As an idea, The Individual replaced the idea of the Divine Right of Kings (Phrontisterion essay, February 2015).

The model for the democratic vision, of course, is European enlightenment, and flows organically from the beheading of the idea of the divine right of kings. When the one king is dead, then ‘We the People’ is assigned the burden of kingship – each one his own little bit. Upon reflection, though, in the democratic model how does one so tie the power of state to the individual, both philosophically and functionally, that the state is ensured a long, even if complex life? Historically speaking, the model of democracy in the west, inspired by the ideas of enlightenment, began life moored to several fundamental principles: participation in the vote; freedom of expression; separation of religious interference from the function and power of the state; and a press that badgers those holding office in order to inhibit the easy spread of corruption.

 

At some point in our reflection there must unavoidably arise an ambiguity, or perhaps it is only a tension, between The Individual conceived of as physis or as kosmos. Up until this point in our reflection, we have been considering The Individual primarily as a cosmetic entity, as an historical idea whose boundaries have been greatly expanded around the periods of enlightenment in the West. This conclusion is generally confirmed among historians of ideas working in just about every field. In his book Escape From Freedom, for example, the social psychologist Erik Fromm (Ch. II) agrees that as an idea, The Individual emerges as a post-enlightenment phenomenon (although he only refers to one period of Western enlightenment, forgetting the phenomenon of Greek philosophy as an enlightenment), maintaining that what he calls the ‘process of individuation’ or the ‘emergence of the individual’ “seems to have reached its peak in modern history in the centuries between the Reformation and the present.”

            However, there is also a more denotative aspect to the idea of The Individual, and that becomes clear when one begins to wonder what it means to be, essentially, “an” individual; what is that ‘whatever’ that is cocooned inside the more connotative elements that accrue to people as a result of their particular historical circumstances? Is there some essential quantity, or quality, that all men share as humans, which also makes them specifically individual? Is there such a thing as an essential and therefore irreducible human nature?

The two general philosophical theories on this question, which Phrontisterion examined in “The Existentialist ‘Project’ & the Ostensible ‘Problem’ of Existence” (November 2013), might be characterized as the Camusian position and the Sartrian position. Camus, following Nietzsche and others in the mainstream of Western philosophical thought, thinks there is an essentialness to men, which, when considered as a collective, makes it meaningful to speak of individual men as collective Man. Sartre, in contrast, depicts man as, essentially, an empty set = {  }, that he is a bundle of possible choices linked to a specific space in time for a while, then not. In this respect, Fromm (op cit, 13) is Sartrian in his thinking about The Individual, for he writes:

It is not as if we had on the one hand an individual equipped by nature with certain drives and on the other, society as something apart from him, either satisfying or frustrating these innate propensities. […] The most beautiful as well as the most ugly inclinations of man are not part of a fixed and biologically given human nature, but result from the social process which creates man. […] Man’s nature, his passions, and anxieties are a cultural product; as a matter of fact, man himself is the most important creation and achievement of the continuous human effort, the record of which we call history.

 

So, up to this point in our reflection we have gained the idea that the history of Western enlightenments has been consistently marked by a shift in the boundaries of men’s view of both themselves as specific objects, as individuum, and of themselves as individual role-players in their world. Both historical shifts toward Western Enlightenment, first in ancient Greece and then in 18th century France, have been characterized by a vision of human reality wherein otherworldliness has yielded the right-of-way to a this-worldly interpretation and expression of Man in his world, with a resulting progression in thinking from the Religious Mind to the Rational Mind.

           

Away from Enlightenment.

            History pauses for neither man nor idea, however, but turns itself over and over constantly in response to “another shake of the kaleidoscope,” to borrow on Maurice Gee’s felicitous expression [Plumb, p. 142]—which only goes to show, once again, the prescience of old Heraclitus the Obscure, that rJei√n ta» o¢la potamouv di÷khn: “It is the way of things […] that, like the currents of the river, the whole [thing] just streams along” (D/K 12, vol. 1, p. 141; cf B12, 91). And as if in historical response to a free-wheeling period of Free-Thinking that followed hard on the heels of the first period of enlightenment, and which has come to be celebrated as the birth of Greek philosophy, along came the onslaught of the Christian Church. And philosophical enlightenment gave way before it.

Consequently, the Religious Mind would hold intellectual sway in Western History until the rise of the second period of enlightenment in Europe, in the 18th century. And in the period following the second period of enlightenment, which is the swinging door connecting to our contemporary world, it would seem that, once again, the Religious Mind is seeking to subjugate or vanquish entirely the free-thinking enlightenment ways of Western Nations and Men. The children of the first enlightenment yielded the floor to the Religious Mind of the burgeoning Christian sect and its beliefs. But at our moment in the historical flow of the West, we, the children of the second enlightenment, are certainly not obliged to make the same choices as their intellectual forefathers. For better, as for worse.

            The Western notion of freedom, which is rooted in the rationalistic notions of The Enlightenment Individual, is not an absolute or eternal value, identical for all men at all times. Not all cultures articulate or value freedoms in the same way; and while the desire to be free may be arguably innate, as Fromm [op cit] thinks, he also suggests that “the human aspect of freedom” coexists within a coterie of deadly rivals, which include the longing for submission, and the lust for power. So, when all is said and done it would seem that far from being static and fixed, the idea of freedom for the individual remains a negotiable quantity—philosophically & politically.

 

Our natural world (physis) spins out on a long thread of heat-releasing entropy… an ongoing give-and-take between order and disorder—and we must make our peace with that. But then this physis-principle must also reasonably hold for the reality that is created by and anchored in the human mind—the kosmos. Such, anyway, was Friedrich Nietzsche’s intuition and insight.

The Age of Religion yields to the Religious Mind, which then yields again to the Age of Reason, which seems to want to, once again, yield to the Religious Mind… and on and on in ceaseless flow like Siddhartha’s eternally flowing river. Which then yields again historically to whatever paradigmatic frame arises that can impose itself in the mix and jostle. And the whole of human history, like the currents of the river with all of its nooks & crannies and ebbs & flows, just keeps streaming along, sometimes quickly sometimes slowly; for human history also plays in the streams of entropy where order (The Age of Religion) submits to disorder (The Age of Reason), and then disorder to order, in a constant dance of ideas.  What is disorder, after all, but the intrinsic nature that frames the essential idea of “freedom”?

 

So, what does it mean to live in the West, inside the Western mindset, governed by Reason and the principles of the Rights of Men? And what happens when there is no longer even a general consensus about the value of the enlightenment mindset (kosmos-disorder), but where the children of enlightenment begin to imagine alternative mindsets other than living in an environment of reasonable enlightenment? Where it becomes possible to imagine cohabitation between the Religious Mind and the Rational Mind? Between order and disorder?

            The Sophists of Plato’s day believed they could improve other men through their wise teaching, but Socrates whole-heartedly disagreed with them (Apology 20B). Yet, if we are to believe Socrates, who is after all Plato’s great ethical hero, and if we really cannot improve one another through wise teaching, then at the end of the day we are left, truly, with only The Individual, who must discover and practice his own virtue. For Socrates, of course, the ideal practice was to follow Justice. If we side with Socrates on this idea that the individual is alone to unveil himself through his practice of virtue (i.e., rightness or justice), then it becomes important for the rest of us, as both spectators and players on the theatrical stages of life, and to whatever degree we wish to exemplify virtue, to take our cues from other fine actors. One man can make the difference. But the cost of making the difference can be exacting, as the pacifist journalist, Jean Jaurès, discovered, who was practically the only man in the whole of France to publicly stand against France and her imperious desire, at all costs, to enter the first world war with Germany. The cost to Jean Jaurès was his life, assassinated from behind in a restaurant. 

 

Have the democratic nations of the West really reached the effective and unsuccessful end of Enlightenment Reason as the framework for self-governance? Is a society governed principally by Reason really just a dystopia patiently awaiting the inevitable return of halcyon days of ordered innocence and goodness dripping like manna from the hand of one god or another? This seems to be Western history’s prophetic narrative, to judge the future of the West by its intellectual history.

            By way of concluding, neither optimistically nor pessimistically, but realistically: in an article entitled kant’s depression, the author suggests that Immanuel Kant anticipated precisely this very unsatisfactory end-point of human reason:

“… What Kant doesn’t consider is that reason might actually be connected to depression, rather than stand as its opposite. What if depression – reason’s failure to achieve self-mastery – is not the failure of reason but instead the result of reason? What if human reason works “too well,” and brings us to conclusions that are anathema to the existence of human beings? What we would have is a “cold rationalism,” shoring up the anthropocentric conceits of the philosophical endeavor, showing us an anonymous, faceless world impervious to our hopes and desires. And, in spite of Kant’s life-long dedication to philosophy and the Enlightenment project, in several of his writings he allows himself to give voice to this cold rationalism. In his essay on Leibniz’s optimism he questions the rationale of an all-knowing God that is at once beneficent towards humanity but also allows human beings to destroy each other. And in his essay “The End of All Things” Kant not only questions humanity’s dominion over the world, but he also questions our presumption to know that – and if – the world will end at all: “But why do human beings expect an end to the world at all? And if this is conceded to them, why must it be a terrible end?”

            The implication in these and other comments by Kant is that reason and the “rational estimation of life’s value” may not have our own best interests in mind, and the self-mastery of reason may not coincide with the self-mastery of us as human beings (or, indeed, of the species as a whole). Philosophical reason taken to these lengths would not only make philosophy improbable (for how could one have philosophy without philosophers?), but also impractical (and what would be the use of such a “depressive reason”?). What Kant refers to as depression is simply this stark realization: that thought is only incidentally human. It would take a later generation of philosophers to derive the conclusion of this: that thought thinks us, not the reverse.

 

Further reading:

·      https://www.nouvelobs.com/les-chroniques-de-pierre-jourde/20201020.OBS34966/aux-musulmans-et-en-particulier-aux-eleves-et-parents-d-eleves-qui-desapprouvent-les-caricatures-de-mahomet.html

 

(Reprised from an original essay published on Phrontisterion on 01/09/2015)

Friday, June 1, 2018

Plato’s Noble Lie and the Psyche of the Philosophical Man



~by David Aiken~

Many and sundry have been the attempts to “get a handle on” a deceptive idea that has its origins in Plato’s Republic—the idea of the Noble Lie. The Noble Lie was never intended to be an element of political theory—this is only the shallow storyline, the theatrical mask that Plato lends to his narrative to throw the profane reader off the track of the sacred richness of his philosophical teaching. In matter of fact, Plato’s Noble Lie is a very clear rational mechanism of Plato’s fully human and fully philosophical ontology; it is not some device to be used for political or state enablement, but rather, it is a constructive philosophical mechanism that enables the 'golden' part of the individual, the rational mind, to construct the individual as a philosophical whole!

One recent transmogrification of the Platonic idea of the Noble Lie was in the 2008 Batman film, The Dark Knight.
At the heart of this dark comic book, cinematographic narrative is the pattern of the black & white, yin & yang quality that defines Everyman. We are none of us entirely white, the Harvey Dent cum White Knights of the world who dare to oppose Evil in the open light of day; nor are we entirely black, the unproblematic embodiments of the unpredictable Joker, the modern Johnny Appleseed of pain and loss, of random suffering and harm.  Rather, Everyman is both of these in differing and mixed degrees. In perhaps our best incarnations we are actually all of us, individually, both the tormented Black Knight, the man-bat, the creature who comes out of the night to drag bad actors and their actions into the light of day, and that complex human creature who, on a much more personal level, is consumed by his personal struggle to make sure that, at least most of the time, the enlightened goodness in his soul that reaches out for justice, overshadows the gnawing, inky hunger of the psychic demon that urges him, almost irresistibly, to punish and to avenge.
            On this telling Harvey Dent fails to live up to one side of his persona by embodying only the White Knight of Justice, and the darkness of his obscured yin overawes the lightness of his aggressive yang. In his high-handed hubris Harvey Dent fails the task of being Everyman; unlike the unusual man-bat who manages, somehow, to balance delicately in the nether regions of his humanity the vital forces of his yin in the light of his yang. In an additional and interesting move, the narrative flow of the film demands that the lead players mask the imperfections of the man under the “persona” of a social Story, behind a myth, a noble lie: that Harvey Dent died heroically in the line of duty, fighting for justice, and in the service of the community. For the “brassy” commoners of the city must not learn that the “golden” man, Harvey Dent, failed; that he turned; that he became mostly lost in the dark. For the sake of the people the Cover Story must not fail; and even if the man behind the mask/myth/Story fails, the Narrative of Justice must not fail; it must remain eternal.
            When all is said and done, this filmic “read” is actually a faithful reflection and reworking of the idea of Plato’s noble lie as it has come down to us in the western thought traditions of philosophy and political theory. And that is unfortunate.

At the risk of sounding adamant, let us just say it right out in the open: Plato’s Republic, one of the perennial great works in the corpus of world literature, which has resided for centuries in the intellectual domain of political philosophers and theorists, is not really about a republic, ideal or otherwise. In the same way that war movies are not about war, i.e., their Subject is not “war,” but rather about Men’s Character and Human Action framed situationally around the thematic of war, so also, when Plato dramatizes a conversation with Socrates around a political thematic, it does not mean that the Subject of the work is political in nature or even anything that is remotely concerned with political thinking. Plato’s Republic is framed around the idea of the City; the City, in turn, is built in the image of Human Ontology, and seeks to answer the question – what is a man? How should a man act? What role does right education play in the evolution of the human mind and soul? In this Platonic metaphor for the philosophical life, as the soul goes, so goes the City.
            If we fail to grasp this distinction between the subject of a work and its opportunistic framing or narrative thematic, then with works such as Plato’s Republic or Machiavelli’s The Prince, once they are construed as politically or philosophically earnest texts, we hermeneuts who come after in the thought tradition are obliged to construct interpretations that correct other interpretations, and in so doing, by committing ourselves to reading literally and failing to read metaphorically, we inadvertently create a whole new set of interpretative problems.
Dr. Frankenstein creating his monster
            For example, by committing to a political interpretation of Plato’s Republic, we also necessarily create as an interpretative by-product an antique Frankenstein in the person of the great Socrates, thereby “disappearing” this irreplaceable thinker behind a political interpretative persona. This tradition’s earnestly-political “read” of the Republic includes almost all the great thinkers, except Augustine, from Aristotle to Machiavelli, and, in the contemporary political philosophical arena, from Karl Popper to Leo Strauss. And, yet, this telling also transforms the story’s hero, the Socrates of the history of philosophy, into the much more well-known Franken-Socrates, once-upon-a-time master teacher of the life of the Just Man, who seems, all irony aside and in great seriousness, to be making the case for Justice and the Just Man by promoting the practice of euthanasia, social classism based on racial purity, selective breeding, and telling noble lies to motivate leaders to act well in the City. Really?!
            This philosophical transmogrification of Socrates is simply too implausible, though, and so the tradition ends up speaking dismissively, or not speaking at all, of the Franken-Socrates it has created, because he is simply too Hitlerian to retain any “street credibility,” philosophically speaking.  This interpretative process is precisely what a sin against Thinking looks like.
            With transmogrifying interpretations such as this, at the end of the day we end up dismissing the work not only because it portrays for us a Socrates qua Machiavellian prince, which violates our politically correct sensibilities, but also because we do not find other cases made in the Republic, such as the case for an ideal state, to be politically persuasive in general. So, the thought tradition that wanders down this interpretative Holtzweg succeeds only in creating an unacceptable political theory and an anti-Socrates—but then, this might have been the intention all along. And perhaps there is some masked man yet “out there” who will come along, some man-bat or Lone Ranger of philosophy, to help us out of the intellectual quagmire created by such a mishmash of non-thinking and pseudo-interpreting on this question of noble lies… Quien sabe, Kemosabe?
             
So, what sense is there to be made of a Socratic statement such as Plato places in of Resp. 377c: "it is imperative for the rulers of the city to supervise the makers of tales," and of the idea of the Noble Lie that follows? In Resp. 414c we begin to learn about this γενναῖον ψεῦδος (gennaion pseudos), which better translates as a false (lying, untrue, mendacious, fraudulent) genealogy (family history). So, our adopted family history, “according” to Socrates, would actually have two parameters. The first is that the citizens of the “Socratic” republic are earth-born, which is to say that we are all inter-related and therefore interconnected. This is a straightforward idea borrowed from the Stoic philosophers. The second parameter is that, as with all that is earth-born, we each contain elements from our Earth-Mother, but not necessarily all the same elements. Some of us are born out of gold metal, some from silver, and others out of bronze and iron. The metal core of the individual will determine his worth and role in the city.
               At face value, at least for politically minded thinkers, the Noble Lie is essential for the political apparatus to maintain stable social structures; it is a lie, in the sense of an “opiate for the masses,” which is force-fed to the masses to subdue them, to keep them happily at their stations in the structures of state. If this argument is teased out literally, we arrive at the conclusion that Socrates promotes, in an ideal kind of way, the practice of euthanasia, social classism, racial purity and separation, selective breeding, and the telling of “lies” to motivate people to behave themselves in their social environment.  
               Yet, this simply cannot be the case, unless, like Mark Anthony before us, we philosophers-turned-Philistines also come to bury Socrates, not to praise him; for it will be true of this Franken-Socrates, as with the many others who have shared similar controlling, manipulating, and authoritarian ideas, that “The evil that men do lives after them.”

However, what if we tease out this argument metaphorically, rather than literally? What if we seek to praise Socrates rather than to bury him? Most philosophers would agree, generally, that there are two ideas that must remain consistent and valid for interpretations of Plato to be plausible. First, Plato the philosopher was clearly a dualist who thought that unchanging truth was possible. Conjecture and Belief, thought Plato, are forms of knowledge linked to the changing world; True Knowledge (or “Seeing”) and Wisdom, on the other hand, are linked to things that are by their nature eternal and unchanging, such as the Forms or Ideas. In this respect Plato shows that he was influenced by the 5th century philosopher from Elea (Southern Greece), Parmenides.
            In his poem, On Nature, which is by and large the most significant fragment still existing from Parmenides, he tells the story of the Young Man who, in his quest for virtue, which is the philosophical or just life of True Knowledge, sees all things (ln. 3) with the same eternal and unblinking Gaze as the Goddess (Muse) (stanza 25-30).  
Meet it is that thou shouldst learn all things, as well
the unshaken heart of persuasive truth, as the opinions of
[30] mortals in which is no true belief at all.

Χρεὼ δέ σε πάντα πυθέσθαι
ἠμέν Ἀληθείης εὐκυκλέος aτρεμὲς ἦτορ
[30] ἠδὲ βροτῶν δόξας, ταῖς οὐκ ἔνι πίστις aληθής.

Where Parmenides speaks in his poem of “opinions” (δόξας), this idea will translate into Plato’s thought as “Belief,” a type of knowing reserved for transient things instead of permanent things; and as this lower form of knowing is juxtaposed over and against True Belief (πίστις aληθής) in Parmenides, so it is as well in Plato, where “Seeing” will be the knowing of eternal truths, of things that are not subject to change because they are transcendental, hence unchanging and permanent.

The second concept that must remain consistent and valid for any interpretation of Plato’s philosophy to be plausible, is that he was enormously impressed by his teacher, Socrates, who was not so much a teacher of Justice, but rather a teacher of the Just Man. Ironically, it is precisely this distinction that allows one to begin unraveling Platonic thought and separating it from Socratic thought. A Platonic Socrates, for example, would typically be expected to articulate some clear teaching on Justice as a permanent and eternal value; this would be consistent with Plato and his love of the Idea/Definition of things. However, this does not seem to be the case in most of the Platonic dialogues involving Socrates, especially the so-called aporetic dialogues. These dialogues are problematic, aporetic, precisely because, in a decidedly un-Platonic move, Socrates does not provide us or leave us with any definition of the virtue desired, such as Piety (Euthyphro) or Justice (The Republic). Instead, the historical Socrates actually argues against such an Eternal Definition of the virtue in question, by showing that any such argument must necessarily contradict itself; and he leaves us understanding and valuing the perception that, as he might well have said behind the scenes of history, we may not be able to find a full-proof definition for Justice, but we can recognize a Just Man from a mile away.

So, in fact, it will actually be the Socrates of history who shows us that Noble Lies, however this idea might be variously interpreted in aftertimes, will have no effect upon the man whose character is not naturally virtuous. A myth or belief of any sort, genealogical, religious, or nationalistic, even though we might be born into it and know nothing else our entire life, will ultimately be for naught if the individual man fails to act out of a fundamental sense of his own character’s virtue. According to Socrates, failure of individual character necessarily trumps any mythological or metaphysical prop; because virtue does not derive from some Belief or other, but rather from individuals who act out of Reasoned Seeing.

So how does this little reflective journey inform those of us who, worlds away from the Greece of antiquity, live in an existential no-man’s land where, possibly for the first time in human history, there is an opportunity for true and authentic individual freedom (for better and for worse) in a land where ancient philosophico-religious mythologies yet still hold sway, and where every variety of nationalism scorches the earth of our souls?

Is truth possible? Plato thinks so, as does Socrates; although their conceptions of truth were quite distinct—Plato’s being framed by an other-worldliness, and Socrates’ by a this-worldliness. Yet either conceptualization of truth would have the effect of bringing like-minded (philosophical) men together, of unifying those who seek to live out the virtuous life. This is one of the true teachings of Plato’s Republic. This philosophical truth stands in obvious contrast to the idea of binding differently-minded men together through any variety of Noble Lie, viz., genealogical, religious, or nationalistic, thus seeking to enslave their emotions rather than to persuade their reasoning minds.

WWNS? What Would Nietzsche Say, perhaps, or a Nietzsche inspired philosopher, about this meandering reflection on noble lies and failures of character?  In the unappeased craving for the freedom to think thoughts that are truly one’s own, and in light of the fact that we are so obviously wandering around lost in the undefined fields of human existential history, Nietzsche might encourage us to break free of all of the noble lies that surround us, or at least as many as we become aware of. A State’s noble lies certainly have no supremacy when measured against the truths of our philosophical wanderings; and the role of a free-thinking res cogitans is, precisely, not to allow itself to be duped by a state’s myths about foundations or origins—beliefs and myths such as patriotism, father- or mother-land, God & Country, among all the others.
           
In The Dance Song, a discourse found in Part II of Nietzsche’s Thus Spoke Zarathustra, Nietzsche helps his reader “feel” the nostalgia that permeates the life lived outside the comforting confines of the foundational myths that surround us, those myths by means of which we construct our very personal identity, and without which we are the ultimate Stranger: at once native, and yet oh so very foreign in this our native land.
An unknown presence is about me, and gazeth thoughtfully. What! Thou livest still, Zarathustra?
Why? Wherefore? Whereby? Whither? Where? How? Is it not folly still to live?—
Ah, my friends; the evening is it which thus interrogateth in me. Forgive me my sadness!
Evening hath come on: forgive me that evening hath come on!"
Thus sang Zarathustra.

Ein Unbekanntes ist um mich und blickt nachdenklich. Was! Du lebst noch, Zarathustra?
Warum? Wofür? Wodurch? Wohin? Wo? Wie? Ist es nicht Torheit, noch zu leben? –
Ach, meine Freunde, der Abend ist es, der so aus mir fragt. Vergebt mir meine Traurigkeit!
Abend ward es: vergebt mir, daß es Abend ward!«

Also sprach Zarathustra.

And what would an individual’s life outside the foundation Stories and Myths look like? How do we recognize the life of the man who is free? The freedom of one’s mind does not necessarily reflect through the life of the individual, although it certainly may; so, frankly, no one really knows.  Nietzsche simply tells us that this transformation of the way our minds think will make of us children again—New Beginnings who are free to explore to our heart’s content. “Innocence,” he writes in The Three Metamorphoses, “is the child, and forgetfulness, a new beginning, a game, a self-rolling wheel, a first movement, a holy Yea (Unschuld ist das Kind und Vergessen, ein Neubeginnen, ein Spiel, ein aus sich rollendes Rad, eine erste Bewegung, ein heiliges Ja-sagen.).” Nietzsche does not seek to validate any particular code of moral behavior; any moral/ethical construct will do the job, including the heroic and virtue ethics, religious ethics and deontology, and all the various incarnations of utilitarian calculations.

As a suggestion, though—perhaps we might adopt as philosophically and ethically unproblematic in this new life of the child, that we may assume the general rightness or propriety of courtesy toward the Other, and kindness, and consideration. This is the stock-in-trade of the Just Man.
            If there are Dissenters from this idea-axiom, then they may abstain from reading further, as they have already clearly abstained, by dissenting from this fundamental valuation of Self in the form of the Other, from thinking humanely about their fellow humans. As they progress along their dissenting path, we may await any and all conduct/thought… for the failure of character, the lack of the will to virtue, is already evident.

There is certainly a dilemma here, though, as we try to imagine a thought-life outside of our Stories; and one can absolutely see why Wittgenstein did not write much in his life. Imagine: here we all are, sitting around at the foot of Wittgenstein’s Mauer des Schweigens, the wall of silence beyond which knowledge is impossible, and so silence becomes the byword… And yet that very silence is equivocal—it has two voices. Because just as the “word” cannot embrace the transcendental “thing,” the thing on the other side of that Mauer of silence, which is by its very definition “no-thing,” nor can a “word” rightly encompass the immanent “thing” on this side of that Mauer. If the word is not the thing, then all it can do is reach up toward whatever inchoate obscurity it is trying to grasp in an attempt to get us, approximately, to some kind of meaning.   At the end of the day, Wittgenstein’s thinking succeeds in reminding us that we are isolated in the time capsule of ourselves, in the closed loop of our own reasoning processes. Pace Wittgenstein, though; for Lady Philosophy still has her role to play in sorting out the noble truths that will help ground the Historical Animal who is slowly descending into the quagmire of fleeting time.

Perhaps, after all, it is for the best that Wittgenstein did not write much.

(reworked from an essay published 1 June, 2014)

Further Phrontisterion readings around the theme of ‘becoming’: